Advance Online Version Volume
2, 2007
Reviews
Alma Mater Matters: Exposing
the Degree Mill Scam
Lisa Richmond
Degree
Mills: The Billion Dollar Industry That Has Sold Over a
Million Fake Diplomas
By Allen Ezell and John Bear
Prometheus
Books, 2005: 230 pages
|
|
This work
is a clear, fact-oriented, and remarkably dispassionate treatment
of a very disturbing subject: the sale and use of fake degrees,
and the generally feeble response of legislators, law-enforcement
agencies, employers, and educators.
Allen Ezell is a former
FBI agent who founded the DipScam project in 1980, “the
first and only time that a government agency attacked the problem”
of fake degrees (16). DipScam ceased operating in 1991 when Mr.
Ezell retired from the agency. John Bear is the author, along
with his daughter, of Bears’ Guide to Degrees by Distance
Learning and similar reference works. The authors point out
that fake credentials have been with us for a very long time,
but the rise of the Internet over the last ten to fifteen years
has enabled this business to really thrive. The authors estimate
that from 1995 to 2005, degree mills have made over a billion
dollars’ worth of sales.
Probably the most extensive
and lucrative degree mill is the “University Degree Program,”
owned by an American and operating its websites and call centers
in numerous other countries. It sells diplomas under the names
of “Lafayette University,” “Northfield University,”
“the University of Switzerland,” and dozens more.
In addition to diplomas, the company provides transcripts, a degree-verification
service for employers to call, and letters of recommendation.
Ezell and Bear estimate that the company’s sales, mostly
to American and Canadian customers, average more than $150,000
a day. Degree Mills includes the text of the company’s
extensive telemarketing script, which the authors got in 2002
from a disgruntled employee.
According to a congressional
study in 1986, the most recent year in which Congress examined
the problem, approximately half a million Americans were actively
using fake degrees (Americans who lie on their resumes, claiming
legitimate degrees that they do not actually have, would form
a separate group). The authors believe that almost all buyers
of fake degrees do so knowingly, and use their degrees with deliberate
intent to deceive. This book has been written for the much smaller
number of people who are seeking a legitimate degree but lack
the ability to distinguish between legitimate and illegitimate
schools. Such naiveté may not be as ridiculous as we think.
While many people know, for example, that legitimate schools are
almost always accredited, they probably do not know that “there
are nearly as many fake accrediting agencies as there are fake
schools” (176). In addition, the increasing variety of online
and other non-traditional forms of education makes judgment more
difficult. One of the book’s appendices contains the first-person
narrative of a woman named Laura Callahan, who resigned from a
senior position in the Department of Homeland Security in 2004
after the media reported on her three degrees from Hamilton University,
a degree mill in Wyoming. She maintains that she fully believed
she was dealing with a legitimate school, and had no intent to
deceive others. The authors stress that there is no definition
that can perfectly distinguish a degree mill from a legitimate
enterprise, since exceptions abound. Instead, they discuss five
aspects of any school that should be considered: what credit is
given for previous work or life experience, how much new work
is required, how the quality of the new work is assessed, who
makes these decisions, and who grants the degrees. The book also
contains a detailed list of suggestions for “how to check
out a school” (133 ff).
The book’s intended
readership, however, is not primarily the small number of prospective
students who need help avoiding what the authors call “less-than-wonderful”
schools. Ezell and Bear have written this book for the general
public, and especially for those who are in a position to do something
once the extent and seriousness of the degree-mill problem is
brought home to them. Why should we care about fake degrees? Without
naming names, the authors list the circumstances of dozens of
people who have used or are now using false credentials to fly
airplanes, practice medicine, serve as expert court witnesses,
work as nuclear engineers, and perform many other critically important
tasks in our society for which trust and real expertise are needed.
The authors even mention someone serving as “head of a national
crime organization” who holds a B.A., M.A., and Ph.D. in
criminal justice—all of which are fake (269). Unfortunately,
professors and academic administrators are not immune from the
temptation, as Degree Mills makes clear. [1]
After the congressional
hearing in 1986, several rather minimal recommendations were put
forth, including the creation of a database of degree-mill information
and a requirement that all federal agencies screen the credentials
of their employees. These recommendations were not put into effect.
The authors show that inaction, weak or non-existent laws, and
disturbing rationalizations are the norm. Degree-mill operators
can be charged under general fraud statutes, mostly commonly wire
or mail fraud, but the penalties are usually weak. A small but
growing number of states have passed legislation specifically
prohibiting the purchase or use of fake degrees.
According to the authors,
the job-hunting website Monster.com currently lists thousands
of resumes containing degrees from known degree mills. Educause,
which supplies the .edu domain name, does not restrict that domain
to legitimate schools only. Along with many other mainstream magazines
and newspapers, the Economist regularly sells degree-mill
advertising. When Ezell and Bear called the Economist to
discuss the ads that appear in this magazine, they were told,
“Our readers are smart enough to make their own decisions”
(121). [2]
The authors point out
that there have been only three other books published in the United
States on degree mills, in 1963, 1986, and 1990, and that academic
research on this topic is almost non-existent. Degree Mills
suggests many recommendations for action, and notes that after
John Bear published an article on this subject in University
Business magazine several years ago, “there were perhaps
a dozen letters to the editor received from university presidents,
all of them of the ‘They should do something!’
variety” (179). Ezell and Bear no doubt hope that the information
contained in Degree Mills will not only spur Them
to act, but cause each of us to determine what we can do also.
Notes
1.
As further evidence, a story in the June 25, 2020 issue of the
Chronicle of Higher Education profiled several professors
at “legitimate” institutions who not only have fake
degrees, but actually own and operate degree mills.
2.
When the Chronicle reporters contacted the legitimate
schools that employ the professors profiled in their story, they
were told that the fake degrees didn’t matter, or that the
professors could run whatever business they wished, as long as
they continued to perform their other duties.
The Structure of Scientific Devolutions
Michael Svoboda
|
The
Great Betrayal : Fraud in Science
By Horace Freeland
Judson
Harcourt, 2004:
480 pages
|
Voodoo
Science : The Road from
Foolishness to Fraud
By Robert L. Park
Oxford University Press, USA , 2001: 240 pages
|
|
|
Undermining
Science: Suppression and Distortion in the Bush Administration
By Seth Shulman
University of
California Press, 2006: 202 pages
|
If you watched the
1998 film, The Matrix, you know the choice: “Take
the blue pill and you wake up in your bed with no knowledge of
what has happened. Take the red pill and you stay in Wonderland,
and I [, Morpheus,] show you how deep the rabbit hole goes.”
With Keanu Reeves, millions of viewers took the red pill. Moments
later they woke up in a fluid-filled pod, tethered to a complex
industrial plant that abruptly excreted them from its system.
Then they were rescued, rehabilitated, and re-educated. They learned
that the late-1990s world in which they had hacked a living was
an elaborate simulacrum created by intelligent machines that farm
humans for their bio-electric energy.
The characters in
the film used many words to describe the grim reality of the matrix,
but “plagiarism,” “fraud,” and “falsification”
were not among them. Nevertheless, these words apply. The machines
did not acknowledge the inventors, designers, and authors of the
sets, props and plots they deployed in their programs (plagiarism).
They presented the matrix for one purpose but used it for another
(fraud). And they made up the data for whole lives just to fit
this purpose (falsification). The reason these otherwise descriptive
words seem out of place in the Matrix is the sheer scale
and pervasiveness of the deception. We feel we are far past the
point where false dealing can be viewed as manageable noise in
an otherwise functioning system. Here the system as a whole is
false.
But at what point is
the line between system noise and system failure crossed? The
three books reviewed here offer different answers to this question.
Of these, the most disturbing is the most recent; it argues that
political manipulation of the policymaking process has resulted
in a simulacrum of science akin to the machine programming of
the Matrix. In the Kuhnian terms invoked by the title
of this review, “normal” fraud has crossed into “revolutionary”
fraud and now poses the risk of a fundamental devolution of science
(Kuhn, 1970, p. 1-9).
Despite the drama
promised by its title, the first book, Horace Judson’s The
Great Betrayal, offers a portrait of normal science that
now, just three years after its publication, seems quaintly reassuring.
Although Judson seeks to persuade us that the necessary and sufficient
conditions for the honest pursuit of research are becoming ever
harder to maintain, his book actually affirms the essential integrity
of science. After all, the frauds that he recounts have been rooted
out, and scientists continue to find ways to circumvent the best
efforts of corporations and governments to withhold information
or otherwise block open and effective communication. Judson’s
efforts to situate recent scientific fraud within broader historical
and social contexts produce a similar result: the contemporary
practice of science looks good by comparison.
Judson begins by observing
that contemporary science is practiced within “A Culture
of Fraud” (pp. 9-42). The examples of Enron, of assorted
stock market manipulations, of corrupt and overpaid tech/com CEOs
suggest that our society extols greed and tolerates the cunning
with which it can be satisfied (pp. 10-18). Does this change
of national heart lie behind recent examples of scientific fraud?
Judson’s first
move to answer this question is to define what fraud means in
the context of science, for which purpose he turns to Charles
Babbage, who, writing in the middle of the nineteenth century,
carefully distinguished four frauds of scientific observation:
hoaxing (deceiving in order to expose folly), forging (making
up data), trimming (discarding data that falls too far beyond
the mean), and cooking (selecting only data that support the hypothesis)
(pp. 46-47). Judson then provides historical examples for
each of these frauds, several of which involve significant figures
in the pantheon of modern science—Isaac Newton, Gregor Mendel,
Charles Darwin, Louis Pasteur, Robert Millikan, Ernst Haeckel,
Sigmund Freud, and Cyril Burt (pp. 48, 52-96). Recounting
the work of scholars who have closely examined the notebooks of
these men, Judson reports case after case of scientists manipulating
their raw data to support their finished theories. Defenders of
these men, Judson notes, argue that it is wrong to measure them
against the standards of contemporary peer-reviewed science. (See,
for example, Wright on Mendel (p. 57) or Holton on Millikan (p.
79)). Judson grants the objection but concludes that we cannot
acquit the charge: we should still be troubled by the small daily
deceptions practiced by these scientists (pp. 95-97).
But the science practiced
by these tainted luminaries was cottage work compared with the
scientific-industrial complex of today, and it is to this much
bigger science that Judson devotes the remainder—and bulk—of
his book. Pointing to the vast growth in federally-funded science,
and to the incentives for forming science empires and dynasties,
Judson argues that science can no longer monitor itself properly
and thus can no longer insure the integrity of its results. This
is “the great betrayal,” the failed promise of science
that Judson chronicles in a series of tales of scientific fraud,
most notably the case of David Baltimore (pp. 191-243).
In all of these cases, blindspots created by hyper-productivity,
by co-dependent mentor-mentee relationships, by honorary authorships,
by harried or compromised reviewers, or by administrators who
managed perceptions before they managed their programs have allowed
faulty or fraudulent studies to be funded and/or published (pp.
144-153). The traditional safeguard against such problems,
the peer-review process, has simply been overwhelmed by the numbers
involved: more scientists, more grant applications, more articles.
And whenever federal funding does not keep pace with institutional
investments in labs and grad students, competition only raises
the stakes higher. Even if she wanted to do due diligence, a harried
researcher volunteering her time for a grant review panel might
not be able to root out more subtle manipulations of data.
Judson examines two
possible solutions to this problem of oversight. The first, the
return of the managing editor, he briefly explores at the end
of his chapter on “The Problems of Peer Review” (pp.
244-286). The second solution, the emergence of open-access
publishing, is detailed in “The Rise of Open Publication
on the Internet" (pp. 325-368). In this rapidly evolving
system, scientific papers are posted online and subjected to endless
correction and revision by publicly identified researchers, rather
than certified just once by anonymous peer-reviewers. Eventually,
Judson concludes, the vast readership of science will collectively
edit most of the science it reads.
While Judson clearly
makes the case that the scale of contemporary science is without
precedent, he never really demonstrates that fraud in science
has grown at the same exponential rate. In fact, one gets the
sense that science remains a calling for many of its practitioners,
that science has successfully encultured the millions who now
inhabit its research stations, labs, and institutes. It is Judson
who has lost his sense of proportion.
Just how close and
closed was the atmosphere that Horace Judson breathed while researching
his story of scientific infidelities becomes clear when one turns
from The Great Betrayal to Voodoo Science. If
Judson’s book is a sort of academic novel, David L. Park’s,
though much shorter, is an epic tale. Much broader characters
fill its pages, men who awkwardly straddle the boundary between
science and self-delusion. These are the figures Park has found
on “the road from foolishness to fraud.”
Although Park does
not mention the movie, this road passes through the Matrix.
One continuous thread of Voodoo Science is the eternal
search for “free energy,” a notion most commonly represented
by the perpetual motion machine. As Park patiently explains, the
goal of free energy, a system that delivers more work (or useful
energy) than the energy put into it, violates some fundamental
laws of physics (pp. 6-7). Claims to have discovered a principle
or to have invented a mechanism that delivers such a bounty are
thus the result either of inept or dishonest accounting for the
energies involved. Such is the case with the bio-electric power
plant that drives the plot and feeds the programs in Matrix.
Farming requires the added energy of the sun; farmers can sell
crops for more than their costs because the light their plants
absorb is free. You cannot farm human energy to replace lost solar
energy. This the authors of Matrix tacitly acknowledge
when Morpheus concludes his description of the bioelectric harvest
by noting that the machines had also discovered “a form
of fusion.” In other words, the real source of the machines’
energy was non-human. Once one actually calculates the energy
inputs and outputs, it becomes clear that raising and deceiving
humans would have been a very expensive hobby for the machines.
But as the many examples recounted in Voodoo Science
amply demonstrate, when it comes to the Second Law of Thermodynamics,
we are all too ready to suspend our disbelief.
Most Americans, in
fact, do not understand these basic principles of energy. Plus,
we have an abiding affection for the underdog, the aspiring, earnest,
and self-taught entrepreneur (p. 5). Add to these two predispositions
our human propensity to perceive and remember only what comports
with our pre-existing beliefs, and we should not be surprised
that Americans are so susceptible to non-science and other forms
of nonsense (“The Belief Gene,” pp. 28-45).
Park recounts several
“discoveries” of free energy, from Pons-Fleischmann
cold fusion (pp. 14-27), to Joe Neuman’s Energy Machine
(pp. 3-8, 98-106), to the Patterson Cell (pp. 10-14,
114-118). A critical marker on the road from foolishness
to fraud, in Park’s view, is the point at which the scientist
or inventor refuses to address legitimate questions about methods,
apparatus, or data, as all of the figures involved in these episodes
tried to do. Carefully maintained isolation is often a precursor
to delusion (“pathological science”) or fraud (“junk
science”) (p.164). If a scientific claim is shielded from
critical inspection by the isolation of its proponent(s), then
it is difficult to replicate that claim. Excessive secrecy regarding
data ultimately render’s that work un-testable (pp. 38-43).
Thus, “secrecy . . . [provides] a haven for voodoo science”
(p. 189).
Although he includes
a chapter on the ways government secrecy fosters foolishness and
fraud (pp. 172-191), in Park’s book it is typically
entrepreneurial inventors who are isolated from the scientific
establishment and who cloak their methods in mystery. In Seth
Shulman’s Undermining Science, by contrast, it
is the political operatives of the Bush administration who shield
themselves from public view while manipulating the results of
publicly-funded science. To read Shulman’s book is to take
one of Morpheus’s red pills: one enters a Wonderland where
the rabbit holes run very deep indeed.
Undermining Science
grew out of a request Shulman received from the Union of Concerned
Scientists (UCS) in 2003 (p. xiii). Concerned then about reports
they were hearing from scientists inside various federal agencies,
departments, and programs, the UCS asked Shulman, an independent
journalist, to investigate. Regular readers of the New York
Times or the Washington Post will recognize many
of the individual stories Shulman has collected; what is new about
Undermining Science is the larger mural Shulman has pieced
together with them. Here is his first sketch of that bigger picture:
Politics always
plays a central role in science and technology policymaking.
Every administration is influenced to some degree by political
consideration on matters of science and technology—as
it should be. What distinguishes the Bush administration, however,
is a dramatic shift: its willingness to stifle or distort scientific
evidence from its own federal agencies that runs counter to
its preferred policies—and ideologies. (p.2)
Shulman draws evidence
for this thesis from across the full spectrum of federally funded
research and administrative fact-finding. The list of suppressions
and distortions is long, but they can be grouped into some broad
categories:
• the editing
of reports and censoring of scientists with evidence of the
anthropogenic causes and the human costs and consequences of
global warming (pp. 16-30),
• the cherry-picking of evidence that supported the administration’s
faith-based claims about abortion (pp. 46-53), abstinence
(pp. 53-60), AIDS (pp. 60-63) and stem-cells (pp.
127-37),
• the stacking of panels and doctoring of evidence for
policies on environmental health hazards like factory farm wastes
(pp. 38-42), lead (pp. 34-38), and mercury (pp.
71-75),
• the shelving of field reports that documented claims
of environmental damage or endangered species (pp. 81-93).
To round out his data,
Shulman includes a brief chapter on the gathering and interpretation
of intelligence in the lead-up to the Iraq War, arguing that the
Bush administration’s top-down imposition of a foreordained
conclusion was of a piece with its suppression and distortion
of scientific data (pp. 94-110).
As portrayed in Shulman’s
Undermining Science, the Bush administration clearly
crossed the line that separates retail interference from wholesale
subversion. While it still sought certification of its policies
as the results of “sound science” (pp. 13-14),
the Bush administration did not arrive at those policies as a
result of any process that could be deemed scientific. Instead,
by installing loyal appointees in critical positions in the federal
bureaucracy, the Bush administration strove to put professional
(i.e. neutral and objective) stamps of approval on its partisan
political policies. Discouraged by these manipulations, career
scientists resigned in record numbers (p. 145). As a result, Shulman
concludes, Americans will still be dealing with the consequences
of his administration’s attack on science years after Bush
has left office (pp. 145-158).
With these three books,
then, we have three different views on the possible breakdown,
or devolution, of science.
According to Horace
Freeland Judson, once science becomes an industry, once the need
for funding and publication become matters of economic security,
the process of evaluating proposals and reviewing reports is compromised,
and the public promise of science is betrayed. But the evidence
Judson assembles for this broad claim is at best equivocal. From
the era before the science-industrial complex, Judson draws several
examples of falsification, fraud, and plagiarism, enough to question
whether some new threshold has been crossed by the contemporary
examples he reviews in greater detail. Repairs will always be
necessary, but the design of the system seems sound. This judgment
is supported by a recent article in Science, “Boom
and Bust,” (Couzin and Miller, 2007) that reported on the
stiff competition for NIH grants. Now only 8% of first submissions
are funded, compared with 21% just 8 years ago (356) [1].
The problem is not that bad studies are being funded on questionable
grounds but that good studies aren’t being funded at all.
Robert L. Park never
claims that science itself is in trouble, only that the public
continues to have difficulty distinguishing between productive
science and fraud/foolishness. The broader factors he cites to
explain this incapacity are low levels of scientific literacy
and high levels of media-driven hype (pp. 3-27). When scientists,
or their university patrons, succumb to the hype, the results
are almost always non-science—and costly. And when the story
involves one of our Holy Grails, like free energy, even scientists
can be too-ready to suspend their disbelief, as a recent Chronicle
piece on “bubble fusion” confirmed yet again (Vance,
2007). When most of the public receives its science news through
mass media that are increasingly subservient to the market, and
when a significant portion of that market craves quick and easy
solutions, then unorthodox claims will be fetched from afar to
feed that audience’s hunger for the magical and the unreal.
But it is when people
with insulated (and thus untestable) beliefs gain the opportunity
to govern science that science is most threatened. Although Shulman
repeatedly points to the Bush administration’s efforts to
appease its corporate and religious supporters, he never draws
the logical conclusion: Bush Republicans do not believe in peer-reviewed
academic science. To the extent that they believe in science at
all, it is the sort of fix-it science of engineers, applied sciences
that simultaneously assume human priority and yet only human scale.
We should not worry about global warming, for example, because
(a) human welfare (i.e. economic growth) is more important than
“the environment” and (b) humans are too small to
produce any planet-scale effects. This problem of worldviews goes
back to Copernicus and Galileo, two scientists who asserted that
a heliocentric model, rather than an earth-centered one, made
better sense of the data. Like the papal authorities then, the
Bush administration and its supporters now are willing to accept
complex epicycles and to reject conflicting data in order to maintain
their core conviction: man is the center of the universe. When
they gained mastery over the many federal domains of academic
science, they simply imposed their product on the process, as
the recent reports of the Fish and Wildlife Service’s handling
of endangered species studies revealed—yet again (Barringer,
2007).
The simulacrum of
the Matrix, in its own very strange way, was also a human-centered
universe. The machines and their machinations were not seen. The
devastation of the environment was invisible. And causes and consequences
were limited to the human world of the global economy. This is
an optimal structure for scientific devolution.
References
Barringer, F. (2007).
Interior official steps down after report of rules violations.
The New York Times on the Web. Retrieved May 10, 2007,
from <http://select.nytimes.com>
Couzin, J. and Miller,
G. (2007, April 20). Boom and bust. Science, 316, 356-361.[1]
Kuhn, T. (1970). The
Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd Ed., enlarged. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Vance, E. (2007, April
6). The bursting of bubble fusion. The Chronicle of Higher
Education, 53 (31), A16, A19-20.
Wachowski, A. and Wachowski,
L. (Directors). (1999). The Matrix. Warner Brothers.
Notes
1.
The author is not related to the Kurt Svoboda profiled in this
Science article
Plagiary, Falsification, and Fabrication
in American Historiography
Mitchell Meltzer
|
Past
Imperfect: Facts, Fictions, Frauds - American History From
Bancroft And Parkman To Ambrose, Bellesiles, Ellis, And
Goodwin
By Peter Charles
Hoffer
Public Affairs,
2004: 287 pages
|
It may
not be too great an exaggeration to maintain that the American
historians of the present moment best known among the general
public are most famous not for the depth of their knowledge of
the nation’s past, nor the sharpness of their opinions about
the present, but for their very public and scandalous dishonesty.
Peter Charles Hoffer, a professor history at the University of
Georgia and a member of the American Historical Association’s
professional division, the ethical watchdog of the profession,
has written a book examining the four most prominent of these
historians in Past Imperfect: Facts, Fictions, Frauds—American
History from Bancroft and Parkman to Ambrose, Bellesiles, Ellis
and Goodwin (PublicAffairs, 2004).
Hoffer’s book provides a complete and reliable account of
the various accusations of dishonesty lodged against these four
particular historians: Stephen Ambrose, Doris Kearns Goodwin,
Joseph Ellis, and Michael Bellesiles. Indeed, the second half
of the book is devoted to a thorough and judicious review of the
precise charges against each of these authors, the evidence from
which these charges stem, and a fair-minded consideration of their
various responses. For any reader who did not follow these individual
cases when they were first reported in the press, or who wish
to consult an extensive review of any or all of them, Hoffer’s
chapters offer an admirably clear, coherent and well-documented
version.
Hoffer divides these erring historians into three categories:
plagiarists, falsifiers, and fabricators. The astonishingly productive
and consistently best-selling Stephen Ambrose, best known perhaps
for his histories of World War II soldiers, and his narrative
of the Lewis and Clarke expedition, Undaunted Courage,
and Doris Kearns Goodwin, a familiar television pundit, once a
regular guest on PBS’s nightly Newshour, are the
two plagiarists. Both authors have, in the course of composing
their various volumes, simply copied substantial passages from
the work of previous historians into their own text, unattributed,
as if these were their own words. Each offered in footnote the
quoted book, but with a range of pages, no page cited from which
their words had been pilfered. In other words, neither author
abided by the most elementary convention of scholarly integrity,
not to say simple honesty: the use of quotation marks when citing
words composed by others.
Hoffer cites an ample number of passages from both historians’
works to justify the indictment. From Ambrose, to give one of
many instances, we are presented with this description of a radioman’s
training from his book, The Wild Blue:
They began shooting skeet, then progressed to firing from moving
platforms, from small arms to automatic weapons and finally
to heavy machine guns. They learned how to operate the power-driven
turrets, how to sight and swing them and their twin fifties.
And here are the words as originally used by their author, Thomas
Childers, in his book, Wings of Morning:
There they shot skeet with a shotgun, then progressed to firing
from moving platforms, first with small arms, then with automatic
weapons and finally heavy machine guns. He learned how to operate
the power-driven turrets, how to sight and swing them and their
twin .50 calibers.
Goodwin’s practice was largely similar. This quotation from
Goodwin's account of FDR, No Ordinary Time, should suffice
to make clear the egregiousness of these procedures:
Eleanor quickly composed herself, walked back into the living
room, and said in her most disarming manner, "It was kind
of Mr.Aldrich to offer to be chairman, but is it not better
from the point of view of geography to have someone from the
Middle West?" At that, she turned immediately to Chicago
philanthropist and New Deal loyalist Marshall Field; she knew
it would be a bother for him, but could he accept? Though caught
somewhat off guard, Field gave his assent.
Compare the passage to its source in Joseph Lash’s Eleanor
and Franklin:
So Eleanor composed herself, returned to the living room, and
said in her most disarming manner: "It is kind of Mr. Aldrich
to offer to be chairman, but is it not better from the point
of view of geography to have someone from the Middle West?"’
At that, she turned to Marshall Field; she knew it was a bothersome
responsibility, she said, but could he accept the Chairmanship?
Somewhat startled, the Chicago philanthropist and stalwart New
Dealer did.
A student in any self-respecting undergraduate history department
who engaged in this kind of verbal theft would, at the very least,
be issued a stiff warning against plagiarism, pure and simple.
Yet here are two professionally trained and accomplished historians
repeatedly violating the minimum standards of scholarly integrity.
More shocking than the fact of these violations in themselves—accidents
happen, after all, and such prolific professional writers routinely
employ assistants—were their responses when confronted with
their offenses. In both cases, though Ambrose much more aggressively
than Goodwin, they claimed that in the very nature of composing
a historical narrative, assembling notes and quotations, such
errors are more or less unavoidable. Hoffer rightly will have
none of this.
So much for the plagiarists. The fabricator is Michael Bellesiles,
whose startling book Arming America looked poised to
overturn completely the prevailing view of gun ownership in the
early years of the nation’s past. A winner of the prestigious
Bancroft Prize for his book, Bellesiles ultimately stood accused
not of borrowing other’s prose—an offense against
principles of ownership, and elementary fairness—but of
the even more damning sin of willfully twisting data to fit his
argument, indeed of actually inventing some of his data from non-existent
sources. Hoffer reviews all the charges along with Bellesiles’s
explanations, and without managing definitively to dot every ‘i”
and cross every “t”, holds Bellesiles guilty of fundamental
dishonesty, a judgment confirmed by the unprecedented step of
the withdrawal of the Bancroft Prize.
As the falsifier, Hoffer presents Joseph Ellis, the celebrated
chronicler of the Founders in such books as Founding Brothers.
Nothing in Ellis’s historical writing has come under attack
but rather Ellis’s teaching in which he spun imaginary tales
of, among other things, his Vietnam War experiences—of which
he had exactly none. In Ellis’s case, Hoffer argues that
his dishonesty, by encouraging him to cultivate the power of his
imagination, seems to have strengthened his historical scholarship.
Comparing his earlier work, before he began fabricating in class,
and during the occasional book-promoting interview, and his work
afterwards, Hoffer sees a distinct gain in Ellis’s “power
as a writer,” allowing him to develop “the lightening-like
brilliance of the insights into character … that do not
appear in the earlier books” (p. 223).
What is the reader to make of this gathering of plagiarists, falsifiers,
and fabricators? Each offense seems quite distinct; what is their
relation to one another? Which is most serious as a threat to
the integrity of the profession? Alas, Hoffer has nothing whatever
to say about this. The cases are presented as if they are extended
bullet points in a list called Historical Dishonesty.
Not that Hoffer doesn’t have an overarching thesis—he
does; but his thesis, that all these problems derive from a tradition
of American consensus history, is neither persuasive nor altogether
coherent.
Hoffer’s account of what is meant by “consensus history,”
a term coined in 1959 by John Higham in which he criticized the
frequent “homogenization” of American history, is
scattered throughout the first hundred and thirty pages of Part
One of his book. It is generally nationalistic and celebratory.
It is a history of the white Protestant America, systematically
marginalizing the place of African Americans, women, Indians,
religious and ethnic minorities, the poor, and all others who
were not a part of the nation’s socio-economic elite. More
to the point, such history was, according to Hoffer, systematically
biased and routinely “falsified and fabricated by omission
and commission, and substituted opinion for scholarship”
(p. 38). And who were these consensus historians? George Bancroft
and Francis Parkman make it into the title of the book, and a
handful of other earlier historians are cited, but whether all
the historical work before the rise of the relatively recent “new
history”—from works such as Henry Adams’s magnificent
History of the United States During the Administrations of
Thomas Jefferson and James Madison (1889-91) to Arthur Schlessinger
Jr.’s The Age of Jackson (1945)—is likewise
guilty of such intellectual sins Hoffer does not make clear. Indeed
in the handful of pages devoted to Bancroft and Parkman Hoffer
cites not a single instance of their texts so that the reader
is unable to judge the extent to which these earlier historians
were doing what Ambrose and Goodman have done. Indeed, Hoffer
acknowledges that unlike these contemporary plagiarists, when
Bancroft or Parker use passages from secondary works without quotation
marks they do rigorously provide the precise page from which they
borrowed it in a footnote.
And what, after all, is the relation between the systematic bias
of ideological blinders—race, gender, ethnicity, class—to
the kind of plagiarism, falsification and fabrication Hoffer goes
on to discuss? That they often overlap must be so: systematic
bias would seem logically to necessitate some misuse, misapplication,
or selective use of the data. But aren’t these two very
different issues: one, the all but inevitable ideological meta-narrative
behind the storytelling of any coherent narrative history; the
other, the violation of basic standards of intellectual honesty,
including the prohibition against verbal theft?
Whether in fact the whole schematic account Hoffer presents of
American historiography—the long reign of “consensus
history” in all its guises yielding to the post-sixties
“new history”-- is a fair one is an open question:
it is more assumed than argued for in his book. A reader not already
persuaded of this now familiar narrative would have very little
to go on from Hoffer’s presentation. The scattershot effect
of the book’s cumbersome title all too accurately reflects
the unfocused and overreaching quality of his argument. In addition
to his contrast between “consensus history” and the
“new history,” Hoffer weaves in and out of the first
part of his book concerns about the development of the historical
profession from a sociological and economic point of view, the
question of professional standards and official review of historical
work, the public perception of the work of historians, and the
need for both scientific history and a national sense of the past
in which the nation can take understandable pride. When in his
brief conclusion Hoffer claims that observers of these recent
cases of historians’ dishonesty “did not think in
historical terms, or understand the long historical causes of
the crisis, [that] they did not see the long dark side of American
history writing,” it sounds both sensational and unjustified
by anything that came before.
As a balanced, well-document account of the problems some prominent
historians have had with standards of honesty, Past Imperfect
is of genuine value. What, if anything, this recent spate of cases
says about American history as an activity, or a profession, remains
to be seen.
The Propagation of Misinformation:
Archeological
Hoaxes throughout History
Stephanie Vie
|
Frauds,
Myths, and Mysteries: Science and Pseudoscience in Archaeology
By Kenneth L.
Feder
McGraw-Hill,
2001: 352 pages
|
Frauds, Myths,
and Mysteries, now in its fifth edition, [1]
is an engaging introduction to many famous archaeological hoaxes.
Tackling well-known examples in popular culture such as the lost
city of Atlantis, Columbus’ discovery of America, Noah’s
Ark, and water dowsing, Feder devotes a chapter to each myth to
shed light on “unsubstantiated, occult, and speculative
claims” (1991, p. 5) and “highly speculative and unproven
or, at worst, complete nonsense” (2006, p. 10). The author
specifically addresses his book to fellow archaeology teachers
(such as in the introduction when Feder notes that “all
of us who teach archaeology hear [uninformed] comments …
from our students”), but Frauds, Myths, and Mysteries
is useful reading for anyone who wants to learn more about how
misinformation is propagated throughout societies. Because the
author only briefly assesses many different hoaxes over the course
of nearly four hundred pages, this book seems best suited to an
introductory college-level reader. However, as an introductory
text in a course that addresses scientific rationality, frauds
and misinformation, and/or rhetorical awareness of audience, Frauds,
Myths, and Mysteries offers some appealing examples that
will likely connect well with students.
The first edition
of this work was not specifically marketed as a textbook, though
the writing was engaging enough and the complexity level of the
writing was certainly not above the average college student’s
grasp. However, the fifth edition now leaves no doubt as to its
purpose; many changes make the book more classroom-friendly, such
as the addition of short critical thinking exercises at each chapter’s
end and a companion website for educational use. Other textbook-friendly
features include a “frequently asked questions” section
before the critical thinking exercises and a short quick start
guide before the first chapter begins. This guide asks students
to critically analyze claims by asking themselves where the claims
are presented and by whom; how do the authors “know”
they are right; whether others have been consulted and whether
these others are also convinced; and whether confirming data are
presented. These factors are all offered to encourage students
to consider whether they have sufficient evidence to make an informed
decision about issues. This critical material is provided, of
course, in the hopes that students will apply these analysis tools
to their archeological studies—and perhaps to Frauds,
Myths, and Mysteries itself.
The companion website
offered at <http://www.mhhe.com/frauds5>
showcases a companion video guide (a seven-page summary of videos
related to the topics covered in the book), the URLs for websites
highlighted in the book’s brief “best of the Web”
notes, and quizzes. Finally, throughout the book students are
presented with additional research sources, such as a list on
page 13 of “skeptical publications on extreme claims not
directly related to archaeology” covering topics like astrology,
the Bermuda triangle, faith healing and miracles, Holocaust denial,
UFOs, and urban legends. These additional sources enhance the
material provided by Feder to give a broader perspective of a
field often colloquially referred to as “myth-busting.”
Although all these changes certainly make Frauds, Myths, and
Mysteries a better textbook, they do detract a bit from the
more scholarly nature of the first edition. Whether this is good
or bad depends on individual perspective and need, of course—for
instance, the reader should question whether this book is intended
for use in a class or as an academic resource. The fifth edition
seems more solidly in the “textbook” camp and indeed,
Frauds, Myths, and Mysteries is a popular choice in many
introductory archaeology and anthropology courses.
Frauds, Myths,
and Mysteries is organized in an easy-to-follow, one-topic-per-chapter
format. Though Feder systematically uses each chapter to debunk
a single fraud or myth (except for the second-to-last chapter,
which deals with three separate religious myths), his goal for
the book “is not to simply debunk individual claims …
the aim here is to put the analysis of such claims firmly within
the perspective of the scientific method as it relates to archaeology”
(vi). To set up this perspective from the beginning, the author
begins by relating his own personal trajectory of interest in
this project, then systematically explains epistemological reasoning
in the second chapter, “Epistemology: How You Know What
You Know.” Feder rather quickly moves away from epistemology
to a more basic understanding of the scientific method. He methodically
describes how scientists understand the world through the inductive
and deductive processes using examples such as childbed fever
in Vienna in the late nineteenth century. [2]
Feder’s goal is to provide the uninitiated reader with an
understanding of the scientific method (testing hypotheses, deducing
implications, and using experiments to uphold scientific theories)
so they will understand why chapters three through twelve follow
the same general format: outline the fraud or myth; show, using
scientific evidence, the falsity of the claim(s); and provide
“current perspectives” on the issue along with frequently
asked questions from students.
For example, Feder
outlines the history of the Cardiff Giant in chapter three. The
giant, rumored to be the fossilized remains of a prehistoric man
discovered in Cardiff, New York, in 1869, was actually a fairly
elaborate gypsum fake—and a fairly lucrative fake at that,
bringing in millions of dollars by today’s standards (p.
51). The Cardiff Giant was exposed because one of the men behind
the fraud, George Hull, confessed after rumors and suspicion began
to circulate. Feder addresses the concepts of authenticity and
belief in the brief “current perspectives” section
at the end of chapter three. The Cardiff Giant myth was dispelled
after skeptics proved it was made from gypsum, a soft stone that
would have broken down in the soil long before the “discovery”
of the supposed petrified man. However, the Giant was widely famous
before it was discredited; many people were apparently taken in,
believing the remains were actually the petrified carcass of a
prehistoric man. Feder asserts that no one would be fooled by
such a “shabby hoax” today. Thanks to more sophisticated
technological tools, scientists can now rely on radiocarbon dating,
scanning electron microscopes, ion microprobes and the like to
discern the validity of archeological finds. Still, the power
of the human capacity to believe despite evidence may prove Feder
wrong—even today near where I live in Tucson, Arizona, residents
of Sedona, Arizona believe in the healing power of the red rocks
and “magical” vortices.
The frauds Feder describes
in successive chapters grow more complex; as time has passed and
science has become more sophisticated, so too have the tools available
to potential charlatans. Chapter four points out the “inelegant
fake” (p. 86) of the Piltdown man fossil, supposedly a missing
link in our evolutionary history that would prove the human brain
evolved long before the modernization of the human body. Though
the identity of the person(s) responsible for the Piltdown fake
remains unknown, it is not so much “whodunnit” (p.
78) as why. Why did people so readily accept the shoddy fake Piltdown
skull at—if you’ll pardon the pun—face value?
Feder points out a truism applicable to all fields of inquiry
and particularly pertinent for writing instructors. Whether out
of naïveté, a refusal to accept that individuals might
purposefully trick one another, or because it is more comfortable
to believe a lie (p. 86), Feder argues that we believe what we
want to believe, often despite evidence to the contrary. As a
college writing instructor, I have found myself in the past wanting
to believe that a suspicious paper was not plagiarized. I wanted
to believe that no student I taught would ever possibly plagiarize.
This desire was further complicated by the institutional difficulties
that accompany an accusation of plagiarism; I must figure out
where the student plagiarized from, perhaps fill out forms detailing
the accusation, meet with the student and perhaps re-grade the
assignment, and so on. (And, much like the rigorous collection
of evidence that Feder points to as necessary to expose myths
and mysteries, instructors who wish to accuse a student of plagiarism
must often collect enough evidence to prove their case, often
using plagiarism detection services and the like.) Like accepting
frauds because it is easier than potentially overturning already-entrenched
belief systems, it is often easier to turn a blind eye to plagiarism
than to challenge suspicious writing. However, Feder clearly believes
in setting the record straight by providing evidence to prove
accepted myths wrong. Similarly, most researchers who study plagiarism
and falsification would assert that exposing fraud and complicating
accepted ideas about plagiarism is a worthy goal.
While “believing
because we want to believe” is a major theme throughout
the book, a second theme emerges in chapter two and runs throughout
the book as well. Feder tackles the division between science and
theology, two areas that “are often forced to part company
and respectfully disagree” (p. 26), by addressing the Shroud
of Turin, Noah’s Ark, and the biblical Flood. The book’s
undercurrent of religious skepticism comes to a head in chapter
eleven, “Old Time Religion—New Age Harmonics.”
In the 1991 edition, Feder begins by likening scientific belief
in religious artifacts to an Indiana Jones movie:
Indiana Jones did manage to recover the Ark of the Covenant—the
receptacle for God’s word as described in the Old Testament—from
the Nazi band that wished to control the enormous power contained
within. Maybe Indy’s next adventure could involve archaeological
proof of the God of the Bible. (1991, p. 171)
In the fifth edition, references to Indiana Jones have
been stripped, but the tone remains the same: “The scientists
have uncovered concrete proof of a miracle and, at least indirectly,
proof of the existence of God. … [this scene] reflects actual
claims made on a number of occasions by self-styled scientists”
(2006, p. 278). Feder goes on to argue that “self-styled
scientists” who believe in artifacts like the Shroud of
Turin have essentially stepped over into the realm of archaeological
debate and are therefore subject to available scientific tests:
Although the purpose of this book is certainly not to assess
the veracity of anyone’s religious beliefs or to judge
the philosophical basis of anyone’s faith, when individuals
claim that there is physical, archaeological evidence for a
basic belief of a particular religion, the argument is removed
from the field of theological discourse and placed squarely
within the proper boundaries of archaeological discussion. (p.
278)
My only issue with
Feder’s treatment of the tensions between scientific belief
and religious faith is his occasional reliance on sarcastic dismissal
of religious beliefs. Chapter eleven mostly proceeds along the
same formula that guides the previous chapters—introduce
the fraud, provide scientific evidence of the deception, and give
a current perspective on historical events—but the author
intermittently sidesteps the issue at hand to deliver comments
like these:
Many creationists
believe that dinosaurs lived during Noah’s time and were
among the animals saved on the Ark (Taylor 1985a). Obviously,
a 30-ton, 40-foot-tall, 100-foot-long Supersaurus would
have been more than a little cramped in its quarters. (p. 285)
Sarcasm regarding
dinosaurs aside, Feder provides sufficient scientific evidence
to prove his point in this chapter, even going so far as to turn
to biblical references when it serves his purpose (such as pointing
out on page 301 that there are no mentions of a mysterious image
on Christ’s burial shroud anywhere in the Gospels). As a
rhetorician, I find Feder’s occasionally invective tone
off-putting; particularly in the 1991 edition, his tone often
slides dangerously close to an ad hominem attack. However,
the eleventh chapter is the only one in which the author’s
anti-religious invective really surfaces, and then it is still
balanced by a reliance on facts, figures, and other scientific
evidence. And, admittedly, Feder’s tone is less sarcastic
in the fifth edition than in the first; for instance, while he
paints creationists as “lame” and “laughable”
threats to scientific rationality in his 1991 text, Feder refers
to these same creationists as simply “weak and unoriginal”
(p. 286) in 2006, attacking the strength of their evidence rather
than their character—a crucial rhetorical shift. Still,
Feder is at his strongest when he is explaining his view of scientific
rationality; I hate to see him contributing to the perpetual tension
between science and religion using sarcasm and dismissal.
Frauds, Myths,
and Mysteries ends with “Real Mysteries of a Verifiable
Past,” where Feder outlines the mysteries of European cave
painters, Mayan civilization and its collapse, Stonehenge, and
crop circles. He ends by again imploring the reader to make informed
decisions about history based on critical analysis of available
evidence: “Many different possible pasts can be constructed
… not all of these constructed pasts—not all of the
possibilities—are equally plausible” (p. 331). Frauds,
Myths, and Mysteries remains a useful addition to the field
of archaeology and a potentially helpful text for courses with
a rhetorical basis (this textbook would be excellent for a unit
on evaluating evidence, analyzing claims, and presenting an argument).
As well, it is an interesting read for anyone who wants to know
more (albeit in brief) about many captivating strands of misinformation
in our culture.
Notes
1.
This review addresses the fifth edition (2006) of Frauds,
Myths, and Mysteries but occasionally references changes
made between the first edition (Mountain View, CA: Mayfield Publishing
Company, 1991) and the fifth.
2. Ignaz Semmelweis, a Hungarian
physician, was credited as discovering the importance of hygiene
in obstetrics after testing numerous hypotheses regarding high
mortality rates for women in a Viennese maternity ward. Feder
outlines the process of Semmelweis’ discovery but does not
address the fact that few in the medical community initially believed
in his assertions. Considering that Feder spends most of his time
in Frauds, Myths, and Mysteries outlining how “we
believe what we want to believe” despite evidence to the
contrary, Semmelweis’ own story would have been a powerful
demonstration of how even the scientific community sometimes refuses
to believe in factual evidence.
Reviews
forthcoming:
(query
editor if interested in reviewing other titles)
Plagiarism
and Literary Property in
the Romantic Period
By Tilar J. Mazzeo
University
of Pennsylvania Press, 2007: 256 pages
|
|
|
The
Little Book of Plagiarism
By Richard A.
Posner
Pantheon, 2007:
128 pages
|
Reviews
invited:
(query
editor if interested in reviewing other titles)
Steal
This Music: How Intellectual Property Law Affects Musical
Creativity
By Joanna Demers
University
of Georgia Press, 2006: 200 pages
|
|
|
The
Deceivers: Art Forgery and Identity in
the Nineteenth Century
By Aviva Briefel
Cornell University
Press, 2006: 256 pages
|
Scientific
Examination of Documents: Methods and Techniques, 3rd Ed.
By David Ellen
CRC Press,
2006: 248 pages
|
|
Review Archive, 2007
Review Archive, 2006
|